Oxford University Press's
Academic Insights for the Thinking World

Zeno of Elea shows Youths the Doors to Truth and False

Is motion an illusion of the senses?

According to Aristotle, Zeno of Elea (ca. 490 – ca. 430 BCE) said, “Nothing moves because what is traveling must first reach the half-way point before it reaches the end.”

One interpretation of the paradox is this. To begin a trip of a certain distance (say 1 meter), a traveler must travel the first half of it (the first 1/2 m), but before he does that he must travel half of the first half (1/4 m), and in fact half of that (1/8 m), ad infinitum. Since there will always exist a smaller first half to be traveled first, Zeno questions whether a traveler can ever even start a trip. The paradox is this: while on the one hand, Zeno’s argument, which questions the very ability to even start a trip, is logical; on the other hand, all around us we see things moving. Hence, either Zeno’s reasoning is flawed or what we see is false.

Proposed solutions have often aimed to find a flaw in Zeno’s reasoning. However, empowered by Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle of quantum mechanics, we’ll argue in favor of Zeno that at best, the phenomenon of mo­tion is experimentally unverifiable! The uncertainty principle discusses how nature limits our ability to make exact measurements regardless of how smart or patient we are or the sophistication of our experimental apparatus. A dramatic consequence of the uncertainty principle is this: observations are disconnected, discrete events; consecutive observations have time and space gaps—we can observe nature only discontinuously. Roughly speaking, it is as if we are observing nature by continuously blinking—our observations are discontinuous, dotted, intermittent, quantum! The concept of continuity in observation must be dismissed. It is a false habit of the mind cre­ated by the observations of macroscopic (daily) phenomena such as, for example, a flying arrow, for which the space and time gaps are undetectably small (due to the arrow’s relatively large mass), although not zero, giving the illusion of continuity in observation. Discontinuity in observation however cannot be ignored when trying to observe microscopic phenomena such as tiny-mass electrons. And without the ability to observe continuously, motion becomes an ambiguous phenomenon. How so?

Motion occurs when during a time interval a particle (e.g., an electron) changes positions with regard to some observer; a particle should be now here and later there in order to say that it moved. But since (according to the uncertainty principle ) nature does not allow us to keep a particle under continuous observation and follow it in a path, and also since a particle is identical to all other particles of the same family (for example, all electrons are identical), it is impossible to determine whether, say, an electron observed in one position has moved there from another position, or whether it is really one and the same electron with that observed in the previous position, regard­less of their proximity. Since observations are disconnected, discrete events—with time (and space) gaps in between, during (and within) which we don’t know what a particle might be doing—subsequent observations of identical particles might in fact be observations of two different particles belonging in the same family and not observations of one and the same particle that might have moved from one position (that of the first observation) to the next (that of a subsequent observation). Without the ability to determine experimentally whether a particle has changed position, its motion—and motion in general—is a questionable concept.

In summary, without the ability to keep a particle under continuous obser­vation, it is impossible to establish experimentally its identity, and therefore it is also impossible to experimentally verify that it has moved. In a sketchy analogy, because of the uncertainty principle, observations of tiny particles happen like so: you see a pawn on a square of a chess­board. Then you close your eyes for a bit. Upon reopening your eyes, you see pawn on another square. Now, since you don’t know if your observations are of the same pawn (recall, pawns, like electrons, are all identical), and also since you haven’t really seen any pawn moving (for your eyes were closed between observations), in strict truth, a pawn’s (like an electron’s) motion is, to say the least, ambiguous. The analogy is not perfect because unlike a pawn, which appears at rest when observed, an electron is observed neither in motion nor at rest—just that it exists somewhere when observed.

Trying to capture the peculiar consequences of the uncertainty principle  on observing and on motion, physicist J. Robert Oppenheimer wrote: “If we ask, for instance, whether the position of the electron remains the same, we must say ‘no’; if we ask whether the electron’s position changes with time, we must say ‘no’; if we ask whether the electron is at rest, we must say ‘no’; if we ask whether it is in motion, we must say ‘no.’”

Indeed, motion is not an experimentally verifiable phenomenon. Speak of the illusion of the senses.

Featured image: Zeno of Elea shows Youths the Doors to Truth and False (Veritas et Falsitas) by Pellegrino Tibaldi via Public domain [PD-US]

Recent Comments

  1. Dr. Arlette Poland

    Thank you for this wonderful article. I just wrote about movement and how nothing is stable, even the chair or desk, or building.

    I wish I had read your article first…! I look forward to reading your books… and hope someday to meet you and learn more! Thank you, again.

  2. Rudy Troike

    This seems to ineluctably connect with the recent anthropocentriic question as to whether there is such a thing as time. (Or with the earlier question of whether if a tree falls in the forest and there is no one around to hear it, was there any sound?) Photographic plates show the paths of gamma rays, etc. Are we in reality merely talking about our own species-specific neurological-perceptual limitations, or built-in genetic constraints on our ideational conceptual ability?

  3. Demetris Nicolaides

    Dear Arlette and Rudy, thanks!

    In loop quantum gravity—an experimentally unverified theory that combines relativity and quantum mechanics—time doesn’t exist; it is an emergent property. But the true nature of space and time are still open questions.

    The tree, or a similar question which had long been debated between Einstein and Niels Bohr, is this: does the moon exist if I’m not looking at it? Einstein (subscriber of an objective reality, influenced by his relativity) thought yes. Thus the fallen tree makes a sound even if he is not there to hear it. But Bohr (subscriber of a subjective reality, influenced by his Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics) thought no—there is neither a moon nor a sound when he is not observing/measuring.

    The “paths” in photographic plates (or cloud chambers) are really the average result of many disconnected (dotted) electron-photon events. Just like these different dots, ………… , which form a path when connected (or appear connected when seen from afar), the electron-photon events in a cloud chamber (being so close to each other because they are so many, although still disconnected) create the illusion of a well-defined path of a single electron (or a gamma photon/ray) in motion. But in truth, the discontinuity in observation of these events (due to the uncertainty principle) doesn’t allow us to causally connect the electron (or the gamma photon) of the one dot/event with that of the neighboring thus we can’t claim that a particle has moved in a path. Besides, if we assume that a photon is emitted from say point A (making that point visible), then that same photon couldn’t have also been emitted from say point B—the photon from B must be different; hence we can’t say a photon (or a ray) has a path from A to B. The apparent “path” of a light ray on a plate or in cloud chamber is an illusion of the senses created by the many, discrete, and closely spaced similar events. So the drawing of say an electron orbiting the nucleus of an atom, is not truth; it is rather convenience—a first practical approach in our teachings of the properties of atoms and of matter in general.

    On the last question, I’m certainly limited in both the mind and the senses :-).

    Thanks!

  4. Graham Relf

    I have often wondered whether a major reason why it is so difficult to define quantum gravity is that we cannot define quantum acceleration so Einstein’s fundamental principle cannot apply.

Comments are closed.